LeviStrauss1951: Difference between revisions

From Dickinson College Wiki
Jump to navigationJump to search
Alvaradr (talk | contribs)
New page: Language and the Analysis of Social Laws Claude Lévi-Strauss American Anthropologist, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2. (Apr. -Jun., 1951), pp. 155-163. Stable URL: http://links.jst...
 
No edit summary
 
(35 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
Language and the Analysis of Social Laws
{{ANTH245_2007_NAV}}


Claude Lévi-Strauss
'''Language and the Analysis of Social Laws'''


American Anthropologist, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2. (Apr. -Jun., 1951), pp. 155-163.
Claude Lévi-Strauss
Stable URL:


http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-7294%28195104%2F06%292%3A53%3A2%3C155%3ALATAOS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-F
American Anthropologist, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2. (Apr. -Jun., 1951), pp. 155-163.


Stable URL: [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-7294%28195104%2F06%292%3A53%3A2%3C155%3ALATAOS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-F JSTOR Link]


= Wiener's view of social science and cybernetics =
= Can there be a cybernetic anthropology? =


IN A recent work, whose importance from the point of view of the future
== Wiener doesn't think so ==
of the social sciences can hardly be overestimated, Wiener poses, and re-
solves in the negative, the question of a possible extension to the social sciences
of the mathematical methods of prediction which have made possible the
construction of the great modern electronic machines. He justifies his position
by two arguments.[1]


== The problem of reflexivity (as I call it) ==
IN A recent work, whose importance from the point of view of the future of the social sciences can hardly be overestimated, [[wikipedia:Norbert_Wiener|Wiener]] poses, and re- solves in the negative, the question of a possible extension to the social sciences of the mathematical methods of prediction which have made possible the construction of the great modern electronic machines. He justifies his position by two arguments.[1]


In the first place, he maintains that the nature of the social sciences is
=== The problem of reflexivity (as I call it) ===
such that it is inevitable that their very development must have repercussions
on the object of their investigation. The coupling of the observer with the
observed phenomenon is well known to contemporary scientific thought, and,
in a sense, it illustrates a universal situation. But it is negligible in fields which
are ripe for the most advanced mathematical investigation; as, for example,
in astrophysics, where the object has such vast dimensions that the influence
of the observer need not be taken into account, or in atomic physics, where the
object is so small that we are only interested in average mass effects in which
the effect of bias on the part of the observer plays no role. In the field of the
social sciences, on the contrary, the object of study is necessarily affected by
the intervention of the observer, and the resulting modifications are on the
same scale as the phenomena that are studied.


== The problem of the short run ==
In the first place, he maintains that the nature of the social
sciences is such that it is inevitable that their very development
must have repercussions on the object of their investigation. The
coupling of the observer with the observed phenomenon is well known to
contemporary scientific thought, and, in a sense, it illustrates a
universal situation. But it is negligible in fields which are ripe for
the most advanced mathematical investigation; as, for example, in
astrophysics, where the object has such vast dimensions that the
influence of the observer need not be taken into account, or in atomic
physics, where the object is so small that we are only interested in
average mass effects in which the effect of bias on the part of the
observer plays no role. In the field of the social sciences, on the
contrary, the object of study is necessarily affected by the
intervention of the observer, and the resulting modifications are on
the same scale as the phenomena that are studied.
=== The problem of the short run ===


In the second place, Wiener observes that the phenomena subjected to  
In the second place, Wiener observes that the phenomena subjected to
sociological or anthropological inquiry are defined within our own sphere of  
sociological or anthropological inquiry are defined within our own
interests; they concern questions of the life, education, career, and death of  
sphere of interests; they concern questions of the life, education,
individuals. Therefore the statistical runs available for the study of a given  
career, and death of individuals. Therefore the statistical runs
phenomenon are always far too short to lay the foundation of a valid induction.  
available for the study of a given phenomenon are always far too short
Mathematical analysis in the field of social sciences, he concludes, can bring  
to lay the foundation of a valid induction. Mathematical analysis in
results which should be of as little interest to the social scientist as those of  
the field of social sciences, he concludes, can bring results which
the statistical study of a gas would be to an individual about the size of a  
should be of as little interest to the social scientist as those of
molecule.  
the statistical study of a gas would be to an individual about the
size of a molecule.


= Response =  
== But Wiener focuses on one kind of data ==


== Wiener focuses on the wrong sort of data ==
These objections seem difficult to refute when they are examined in
terms of the investigations toward which their author has directed
them, the data of research monographs and of applied anthropology. In
such cases, we are deal- ing with a study of individual behavior,
directed by an observer who is him- self an individual; or with a
study of a culture, a national character, or a pat- tern, by an
observer who cannot dissociate himself completely from his culture, or
from the culture out of which his working hypotheses and his methods
of observation, which are themselves cultural patterns, are derived.


These objections seem difficult to refute when they are examined in terms
== We should use language as our model ==
of the investigations toward which their author has directed them, the data of
research monographs and of applied anthropology. In such cases, we are deal-
ing with a study of individual behavior, directed by an observer who is him-
self an individual; or with a study of a culture, a national character, or a pat-
tern, by an observer who cannot dissociate himself completely from his culture,
or from the culture out of which his working hypotheses and his methods of
observation, which are themselves cultural patterns, are derived.


= Language seems suitable =
There is, however, at least one area of the social sciences where
Wiener's objections do not seem to be applicable, where the conditions
which he sets as a requirement for a valid mathematical study seem to
find themselves rigorously met. This is the field of language, when
studied in the light of struc- tural linguistics, with particular
reference to phonemics.


There is, however, at least one area of the social sciences where Wiener's
=== Language not affected by reflexivity ===
objections do not seem to be applicable, where the conditions which he sets
as a requirement for a valid mathematical study seem to find themselves
rigorously met. This is the field of language, when studied in the light of struc-
tural linguistics, with particular reference to phonemics.


Language is a social phenomenon; and, of all social phenomena, it is the
* Language's rules are unconscious and unaffected by awareness of them
one which manifests to the greatest degree two fundamental characteristics
which make it susceptible of scientific study. In the first place, much of lin-
guistic behavior lies on the level of unconscious thought. When we speak, we
are not conscious of the syntactic and morphological laws of our language.
Moreover, we are not ordinarily conscious of the phonemes that we employ
to convey different meanings; and we are rarely, if ever, conscious of the phono-
logical oppositions which reduce each phoneme to a bundle of differential
features. This absence of consciousness, moreover, still holds when we do be-
come aware of the grammar or the phonemics of our language. For, while
this awareness is but the privilege of the scholar, language, as a matter of fact,
lives and develops only as a collective construct; and even the scholar's lin-
guistic knowledge always remains dissociated from his experience as a speaking
agent, for his mode of speech is not affected by his ability to interpret his lan-
guage on a higher level. We may say, then, that as concerns language, we need
not fear the influence of the observer on the observed phenomenon, because
the observer cannot modify the phenomenon merely by becoming conscious
of it.


Furthermore, as regards Wiener's second point, we know that language  
Language is a social phenomenon; and, of all social phenomena, it is
appeared very early in human history. Therefore, even if we can study it
the one which manifests to the greatest degree two fundamental
scientifically only when written documents are available, writing itself goes
characteristics which make it susceptible of scientific study. In the
back a considerable distance, and furnishes long enough runs to make language  
first place, much of lin- guistic behavior lies on the level of
a valid subject for mathematical analysis. For example, the series we have at
unconscious thought. When we speak, we are not conscious of the
our disposal in studying Indo-European, Semitic or Sino-Thibetan languages is  
syntactic and morphological laws of our language. Moreover, we are not
about four or five thousand years old. And, where a comparable temporal
ordinarily conscious of the phonemes that we employ to convey
dimension is lacking, the multiplicity of coexistent forms furnishes, for several
different meanings; and we are rarely, if ever, conscious of the
other linguistic families, a spatial dimension that is no less valuable.  
phono- logical oppositions which reduce each phoneme to a bundle of
differential features. This absence of consciousness, moreover, still
holds when we do be- come aware of the grammar or the phonemics of our
language. For, while this awareness is but the privilege of the
scholar, language, as a matter of fact, lives and develops only as a
collective construct; and even the scholar's lin- guistic knowledge
always remains dissociated from his experience as a speaking agent,
for his mode of speech is not affected by his ability to interpret his
lan- guage on a higher level. We may say, then, that as concerns
language, we need not fear the influence of the observer on the
observed phenomenon, because the observer cannot modify the phenomenon
merely by becoming conscious of it.  


We thus find in language a social phenomenon which manifests both in-
=== Language is ancient ===
dependence of the object and long statistical runs; which would seem to indi-
cate that language is a phenomenon fully qualified to satisfy the demands of
mathematicians for the type of analysis Wiener suggests.


It is, in fact, difficult to see why certain linguistic problems could not be
Furthermore, as regards Wiener's second point, we know that language
solved by modern calculating machines. With knowledge of the phonological
appeared very early in human history. Therefore, even if we can study
structure of a language and the laws which govern the grouping of consonants
it scientifically only when written documents are available, writing
and vowels, a student could easily use a machine to compute all the combina-
itself goes back a considerable distance, and furnishes long enough
tions of phonemes constituting the words of n syllables existing in the vocabu-
runs to make language a valid subject for mathematical analysis. For
lary, or even the number of combinations compatible with the structure of
example, the series we have at our disposal in studying Indo-European,
the language under consideration, such as previously defined. With a machine
Semitic or Sino-Thibetan languages is about four or five thousand
into which would be "fed" the equations regulating the types of structures
years old. And, where a comparable temporal dimension is lacking, the
with which phonemics usually deals, the repertory of sound which human
multiplicity of coexistent forms furnishes, for several other
speech organs can emit, and the minimal differential values, determined by
linguistic families, a spatial dimension that is no less valuable.  
psycho-physiological methods, which distinguish between the phonemes closest
to one another, one would doubtless be able to obtain a computation of the
totality of phonological structures for n oppositions (n being as high as one
wished). One could thus construct a sort of periodic table of linguistic struc-
tures that would be comparable to the table of elements which Mendeleieff
introduced into modern chemistry. It would then only remain for us to check
the place of known languages in this table, to identify the positions and the
relationships of the languages whose first-hand study is still too imperfect to
give us a proper theoretical knowledge of them, and to discover the place of  
languages that have disappeared, are unknown, yet to come,, or simply possible.  


To add a last example: Jakobson has recently suggested that a language
We thus find in language a social phenomenon which manifests both in-
may possess several coexisting phonological structures, each of which may
dependence of the object and long statistical runs; which would seem
intervene in a different kind of grammatical operation.[2] Since there must ob-  
to indi- cate that language is a phenomenon fully qualified to satisfy
viously be a relationship between the different structural modalities of the same
the demands of mathematicians for the type of analysis Wiener
language, we arrive at the concept of a "metastructure" which would be some-
suggests.  
thing like the law of the group (''loi du groupe'') consisting of its modal structures.
If all of these modalities could be analyzed by our machine, established mathe-  
matical methods would permit it to construct the "metastructure" of the  
language, which would in certain complex cases be so intricate as to make it
difficult, if not impossible, to achieve on the basis of purely empirical investi-
gation.  


The problem under discussion here can, then, be defined as follows. Among
=== Language lends itself to computation ===  
all social phenomena, language alone has thus far been studied in a manner
* Note L-S's conflation of cybernetics with computation
which permits it to serve as the object of truly scientific analysis, allowing us
* L-S shows his interest in database technology here (as elsewhere)
to understand its formative process and to predict its mode of change. This
* Basic idea: structure = elements + rules of combination
  results from modern researches into the problems of phonemics, which have
reached beyond the superficial conscious and historical expression of linguistic
phenomena to attain fundamental and objective realities consisting of systems
of relations which are the products of unconscious thought processes. The
question which now arises is this: is it possible to effect a similar reduction
in the analysis of other forms of social phenomena? If so, would this analysis
lead to the same result? And if the answer to this last question is in the affirma-
tive, can we conclude that all forms of social life are substantially of the same
nature-that is, do they consist of systems of behavior that represent the pro-
jection, on the level of conscious and socialized thought, of universal laws which
regulate the unconscious activities of the mind? Obviously, no attempt can be
made here to do more than to sketch this problem by indicating certain points
of reference and projecting the principal lines along which its orientation might
be effective.


Some of the researches of Kroeber appear to be of the greatest importance
It is, in fact, difficult to see why certain linguistic problems could
in suggesting approaches to our problem, particularly his work on changes in
not be solved by modern calculating machines. With knowledge of the
the styles of women's dress[3] Fashion actually is, in the highest degree, a phe-
phonological structure of a language and the laws which govern the
nomenon which depends on the unconscious activity of the mind. We rarely
grouping of consonants and vowels, a student could easily use a
take note of why a particular style pleases us, or falls into disuse. Kroeber has
machine to compute all the combina- tions of phonemes constituting the
demonstrated that this seemingly arbitrary evolution follows definite laws.
words of n syllables existing in the vocabu- lary, or even the number
These laws cannot be reached by purely empirical observation, or by intuitive
of combinations compatible with the structure of the language under
consideration of phenomena, but result from measuring some basic relation-  
consideration, such as previously defined. With a machine into which
ships between the various elements of costume. The relationship thus obtained
would be "fed" the equations regulating the types of structures with
can be expressed in terms of mathematical functions, whose values, calculated
which phonemics usually deals, the repertory of sound which human
at a given moment, make prediction possible.  
speech organs can emit, and the minimal differential values,
determined by psycho-physiological methods, which distinguish between
the phonemes closest to one another, one would doubtless be able to
obtain a computation of the totality of phonological structures for n
oppositions (n being as high as one wished). One could thus construct
a sort of periodic table of linguistic struc- tures that would be
comparable to the table of elements which Mendeleieff introduced into
modern chemistry. It would then only remain for us to check the place
of known languages in this table, to identify the positions and the
relationships of the languages whose first-hand study is still too
imperfect to give us a proper theoretical knowledge of them, and to
discover the place of languages that have disappeared, are unknown,
yet to come,, or simply possible.


Kroeber has thus shown how even such a highly arbitrary aspect of social
=== An example from Jakobson ===
behavior is susceptible of scientific study. His method may be usefully com-
* Metastructure
pared not only with that of structural linguistics, but also with that of the  
* "Law of the Group" (See
natural sciences. There is a remarkable analogy between these researches and
[[LeviStrauss1955#A_.22permutation_group.22|L-S 1955]])
those of a contemporary biologist, G. Teissier, on the growth of the organs of
certain crustaceans.[4] Teissier has shown that, in order to formulate the laws
of this growth, it has been necessary to consider the relative dimensions of
the component parts of the claws, and not the exterior forms of these organs.  
There, relationships allow us to derive constants-termed parameters-out
of which it is possible to derive the laws which govern the development of these
organisms. The object of a scientific zoology, in these terms, is thus not ulti-  
mately concerned with the forms of animals and their organs as they are usual-
ly perceived, but is to establish certain abstract and measurable relationships,
which constitute the basic nature of the phenomena under study.


An analogous method has been followed in studying certain features of  
To add a last example: [[wikipedia:Jakobson|Jakobson]] has recently
social organization, particularly marriage rules and kinship systems.[5] It has
suggested that a language may possess several coexisting phonological
been shown that the complete set of marriage regulations operating in human
structures, each of which may intervene in a different kind of
societies, and usually classified under different headings such as incest prohibi-
grammatical operation.[2] Since there must ob- viously be a
tions, preferential forms of marriage, and the like, can be interpreted as being
relationship between the different structural modalities of the same
so many different ways of insuring the circulation of women within the social
language, we arrive at the concept of a "metastructure" which would be
group, or, of substituting the mechanism of a sociologically determined affinity
some- thing like the law of the group (''loi du groupe'') consisting
for that of a biologically determined consanguinity. Proceeding from this
of its modal structures. If all of these modalities could be analyzed
hypothesis, it would only be neccesary to make a mathematical study of every
by our machine, established mathe- matical methods would permit it to
possible type of exchange between npartners to enable one almost automatical-
construct the "metastructure" of the language, which would in certain
ly to arrive at every type of marriage rule actually operating in living societies
complex cases be so intricate as to make it difficult, if not
and, eventually, to discover others which are merely possible; one would also
impossible, to achieve on the basis of purely empirical investi-
understand their function and the relationships between each type and the  
gation.
others.  


This approach was fully validated by the demonstration, reached by pure
= The Model of Language =
deduction, that the mechanisms of reciprocity known to classical anthropology
* Language = phonemes + rules of combination
-- namely, those based on dual organization and exchange-marriage between
* "Universal laws which regulate the unconscious activities of the
two partners or whose number is a multiple of two-are but a special instance
mind"
of a wider kind of reciprocity between any number of partners. This fact has  
* Criteria for structure:
tended to remain unnoticed, because the partners in those matings, instead
*# is unconscious
of giving and receiving from one another, do not give to those from whom they
*# has elements
receive, and do not receive from those to whom they give.,They give to and
*# has rules
receive from different partners to whom they are bound by a relationship that
*# does communication
operates only in one direction.
* Grammar is a good synonym


This type of organization, no less important than the moiety system, has  
The problem under discussion here can, then, be defined as follows.
thus far been observed and described only imperfectly and incidentally. Start-
Among all social phenomena, language alone has thus far been studied
ing with the results of mathematical study, data had to be compiled; thus, the  
in a manner which permits it to serve as the object of truly
real extension of the system was shown and its first theoretical analysis ffered.[6]
scientific analysis, allowing us to understand its formative process
At the same time, it became possible to explain the more general features of  
and to predict its mode of change. This results from modern researches
marriage rules such as preferential marriage between bilateral cross-cousins
into the problems of phonemics, which have reached beyond the
or with only one kind of cross-cousin, on the father's side (patrilateral), or on
superficial conscious and historical expression of linguistic
that of the mother (matrilateral). Thus, for example, though such customs had
phenomena to attain fundamental and objective realities consisting of
been unintelligible to anthropologists,[7] they were perfectly clear when regarded
systems of relations which are the products of unconscious thought
as illustrating different modalities of the laws of exchange. In turn, these were
processes. The question which now arises is this: is it possible to
reduced to a still more basic relationship between the rules of residence and  
effect a similar reduction in the analysis of other forms of social
the rules of descent.[8]
phenomena? If so, would this analysis lead to the same result? And if
the answer to this last question is in the affirma- tive, can we
conclude that all forms of social life are substantially of the same
nature-that is, do they consist of systems of behavior that represent
the pro- jection, on the level of conscious and socialized thought, of
universal laws which regulate the unconscious activities of the mind?
Obviously, no attempt can be made here to do more than to sketch this
problem by indicating certain points of reference and projecting the
principal lines along which its orientation might be effective.  


Now, these results have only been achieved by treating marriage regula-
== The example of Kroeber on fashion ==
tions and kinship systems as a kind of language, a set of processes permitting
* About Kroeber's essay:
the establishment, between individuals and groups, of a certain type of com-
** Women’s dress fashion over 300 years
munication. That the mediating factor, in this case, should be the women of
** Skirt length changed in a periodic cycle.  
the group, who are circulated between clans, lineages, or families, in place of
** No direct cause (political or economic cycles) -- cannot be explained by outside factors; evolves according to its own internal laws.
the words of the group, which are circulated between individuals, does not at all
** This independent cultural realm = the "superorganic"
change the fact that the essential ~pect of the phenomenon is identical in
both cases.


We may now ask whether, in extending the concept of communication so as
Some of the researches of [[wikipedia:Alfred_Kroeber|Kroeber]] appear
to make it include exogamy and the rules flowing from the prohibition of in-
to be of the greatest importance in suggesting approaches to our
cest, we may not, reciprocally, achieve insight into a problem that is still very
problem, particularly his work on changes in the styles of women's
obscure, that of the origin of language. For marriage regulations, in relation
dress[3] Fashion actually is, in the highest degree, a phe- nomenon
to language, represent a complex much more rough and archaic than the latter.
which depends on the unconscious activity of the mind. We rarely take
It is generally recognized that words are signs: but poets are practically the
note of why a particular style pleases us, or falls into disuse.
only ones who know that words have also been values. As against this, women
Kroeber has demonstrated that this seemingly arbitrary evolution
are held by the social group to be values of the most essential kind, though we
follows definite laws. These laws cannot be reached by purely
have difficulty in understanding how these values become integrated in systems
empirical observation, or by intuitive consideration of phenomena, but
endowed with a significant function. This ambiguity is clearly manifested in
result from measuring some basic relation- ships between the various
the reactions of persons who, on the basis of the analysis of social structures
elements of costume. The relationship thus obtained can be expressed
referred to,[9] have laid against it the charge of "anti-feminism," because women  
in terms of mathematical functions, whose values, calculated at a
are referred to as objects.[10] Of course, it may be disturbing to some to have
given moment, make prediction possible.
women conceived as mere parts of a meaningful system. However, one should
keep in mind that the processes by which phonemes and words have lost-even
though in an illusory manner-their character of value, to become reduced
to pure signs, will never lead to the same results in matters concerning women.  
For words do not speak, while women do; as producers of signs, they can never
be reduced to the status of symbols or tokens. But it is for this very reason
that the position of women, as actually found in this system of communication
between men that is made up of marriage regulations and kinship nomenclature,  
may afford us a workable image of the type of relationships that could have
existed at a very early period in the development of language, between human
beings and their words. As in the case of women, the original impulse which
compelled men to exchange words must be sought for in that split-representa-
tion which pertains to the symbolic function. For, since certain terms are
simultaneously perceived as having a value both for the speaker and the
listener, the only way to resolve this contradiction is in the exchange of comple-
mentary values, to which all social existence reduces itself.  


These speculations may be judged utopian. Yet, granting that the assump-
== Teissier on zoology ==
tions made here are legitimate, a very important consequence follows that is
susceptible of immediate verification. That is, the question may be raised
whether the different aspects of social life (including even art and religion)
can not only be studied by the methods, and with the help of concepts similar
to those employed in linguistics, but also whether they do not constitute
phenomena whose inmost nature is the same as that of language. That is, in
the words of Voegelin, we may ask whether there are not only "operational"
but also "substantial comparabilities" between language and culture.[11]


How can this hypothesis be verified? It will be necessary to develop the
Kroeber has thus shown how even such a highly arbitrary aspect of
analysis of the different features of social life, either for a given society or for
social behavior is susceptible of scientific study. His method may be
a complex of societies, so that a deep enough level can be reached to make it
usefully com- pared not only with that of structural linguistics, but
possible to cross from one to the other; or to express the specific structure of  
also with that of the natural sciences. There is a remarkable analogy
each in terms of a sort of general language, valid for each system separately
between these researches and those of a contemporary biologist, G.
and for all of them taken together. It would thus be possible to ascertain if
Teissier, on the growth of the organs of certain crustaceans.[4]
one had reached their inner nature, and to determine if this pertained to the  
Teissier has shown that, in order to formulate the laws of this
same kind of reality. In order to develop this point, an experiment can be at-
growth, it has been necessary to consider the relative dimensions of
tempted. It will consist, on the part of the anthropologist, in translating the
the component parts of the claws, and not the exterior forms of these
basic features of the kinship systems from different parts of the world in terms
organs. There, relationships allow us to derive constants-termed
general enough to be meaningful to the linguist, and thus be equally applicable
parameters-out of which it is possible to derive the laws which govern
by the latter to the description of the languages from the same regions. Both
the development of these organisms. The object of a scientific
could thus ascertain whether or not different types of communication systems
zoology, in these terms, is thus not ulti- mately concerned with the
in the same societies-that is, kinship and language-are or are not caused by
forms of animals and their organs as they are usual- ly perceived, but
identical unconscious structures. Should this be the case, we would be assured
is to establish certain abstract and measurable relationships, which
of having reached a truly fundamental formulation.  
constitute the basic nature of the phenomena under study.  


If then, a substantial identity were assumed to exist between language
== Levi-Strauss on kinship ==
structure and kinship systems, one should find, in the following regions of the
* Describes results from ''The Elementary Structures of Kinship.''
world, languages whose structures would be of a type comparable to kinship
* Elements = partners, groups, households
systems in the following terms:
* Rules = incest prohibition, marriage rules, inheritance, locality


1. Indo-European: As concerns the kinship systems, we find that the mar-
An analogous method has been followed in studying certain features of
riage regulations of our contemporary civilization are entirely based on the
social organization, particularly marriage rules and kinship
principle that, a few negative prescriptions being granted, the density and  
systems.[5] It has been shown that the complete set of marriage
fluidity of the population will achieve by itself the same results which other
regulations operating in human societies, and usually classified under
societies have sought in more complicated sets of rules; i.e. social cohesion
different headings such as incest prohibi- tions, preferential forms
obtained by marriage in degrees far removed or even impossible to trace.
of marriage, and the like, can be interpreted as being so many
This statistical solution has its origin in a typical feature of most ancient Indo-  
different ways of insuring the circulation of women within the social
European systems. These belong, in the author's terminology, to a simple
group, or, of substituting the mechanism of a sociologically
formula of generalized reciprocity (formule simple de 1'6change g6n6ralis6).[12]
determined affinity for that of a biologically determined
However, instead of prevailing between lineages, this formula operates be-
consanguinity. Proceeding from this hypothesis, it would only be
tween more complex units of the brastsvo type, which actually are clusters
neccesary to make a mathematical study of every possible type of
of lineages, each of which enjoys a certain freedom within the rigid framework
exchange between npartners to enable one almost automatical- ly to
of general reciprocity in effect at the level of the cluster. Therefore, it can be
arrive at every type of marriage rule actually operating in living
said that a characteristic feature of Indo-European kinship structure lies in
societies and, eventually, to discover others which are merely
the fact that a problem set in simple terms always admits of many solutions.  
possible; one would also understand their function and the
Should the linguistic structure be homologous with the kinship structure
relationships between each type and the others.  
it would thus be possible to express the basic feature of Indo-European lan-
guages as follows: The languages have simple structures, utilizing numerous
elements. The opposition between the simplicity of the structure and the multi-  
plicity of elements is expressed in the fact that several elements compete to  
occupy the same positions in the structure.  


2. Sino-Thibetan kinship systems exhibit quite a different type of complex-
=== Reciprocity as special case of exchange ===
ity. They belong to or derive directly from the simplest form of general reci-
procity, namely mother's brother's daughter marriage, so that, as has been
shown,[13] while this type of marriage insures social cohesion in the simplest
way, at the same time it permits this to be indefinitely extended so as to in-
clude any number of participants.


Translated into more general terms applicable to language that would
This approach was fully validated by the demonstration, reached by
correspond to the following linguistic pattern, we may say that the structure
pure deduction, that the mechanisms of reciprocity known to classical
is complex, while the elements are few, a feature that may be related to the
anthropology -- namely, those based on dual organization and
tonal structure of these languages.  
exchange-marriage between two partners or whose number is a multiple
of two-are but a special instance of a wider kind of reciprocity
between any number of partners. This fact has tended to remain
unnoticed, because the partners in those matings, instead of giving
and receiving from one another, do not give to those from whom they
receive, and do not receive from those to whom they give.,They give to
and receive from different partners to whom they are bound by a
relationship that operates only in one direction.  


3. The typical feature of African kinship systems is the extension of the  
This type of organization, no less important than the moiety system,
bride-wealth system, coupled with a rather frequent prohibition on marriage
has thus far been observed and described only imperfectly and
with the wife's brother's wife. The joint result is a system of general reciproc-  
incidentally. Start- ing with the results of mathematical study, data
ity already more complex than the one with the mother's brother's daughter,  
had to be compiled; thus, the real extension of the system was shown
while the types of unions resulting from the circulation of the marriage-price
and its first theoretical analysis ffered.[6] At the same time, it
approaches, to some extent, the statistical mechanism operating in our own
became possible to explain the more general features of marriage rules
society.  
such as preferential marriage between bilateral cross-cousins or with
only one kind of cross-cousin, on the father's side (patrilateral), or
on that of the mother (matrilateral). Thus, for example, though such
customs had been unintelligible to anthropologists,[7] they were
perfectly clear when regarded as illustrating different modalities of
the laws of exchange. In turn, these were reduced to a still more
basic relationship between the rules of residence and the rules of
descent.[8]


Therefore one could say that African languages have several modalities
== The result of viewing kinship and marriage as communication ==
corresponding in general to a position intermediate between 1) and 2).
* Clothing and women are signals


4. The widely recognized features of Oceanic kinship systems seem to lead
Now, these results have only been achieved by treating marriage
to the following formulation of the basic characteristics of the linguistic pat-
regula- tions and kinship systems as a kind of language, a set of
tern: simple structure and few elements.  
processes permitting the establishment, between individuals and
groups, of a certain type of com- munication. That the mediating
factor, in this case, should be the women of the group, who are
circulated between clans, lineages, or families, in place of the words
of the group, which are circulated between individuals, does not at
all change the fact that the essential ~pect of the phenomenon is
identical in both cases.  


5. The originality of American kinship systems lies with the so-called Crow-
= The Origin of Language =
Omaha type which should be carefully distinguished from other types showing
-the same disregard for generation levels.[14] The important point with the Crow-
Omaha type is not that two kinds of cross-cousins are classified in different
generation levels, but rather that they are classified with consanguineous kin
instead of with affinal kin as it occurs, for instance, in the Miwok system. But
systems of the Miwok type belong equally to the Old and the New World;
while when considering the differential systems just referred to as Crow-
Omaha, one must admit that, apart from a few exceptions, these are only typi-
cal for the New World. It can be shown that this quite exceptional feature of
the Crow-Omaha system results from the simultaneous application of the two
simple formulas of reciprocity, both special and general (tchange restreint and
echange generalise),[15] which elsewhere in the world were generally considered
to be incompatible. It thus became possible to achieve marriage within remote
degrees by using simultaneously two simple formulas, each of which independ-
ently applied could only have led to different kinds of cross-cousin marriages.
The linguistic pattern corresponding to that situation would be that cer-
tain of the American languages offer a relatively high number of elements,
which succeed in becoming organized into relatively simple structures by com-
pelling these to assume an asymmetrical form.


It must be kept in mind that in the above highly tentative experiment, the  
== Kinship may help shed light on the origin of language ==
anthropologist proceeds from what is known to what is unknown to him:
* Kinship is more static and has more data
namely from kinship structures to linguistic structures. Whether or not the
* If it is a communication system, and if all communication systems share a common code, then kinship theory can shed light on language
differential characteristics thus outlined have a meaning in so far as the re-
* "The original impulse which compelled men to exchange words must be sought for in that split-representation which pertains to the symbolic function."
spective languages are concerned, remains for the linguist to decide. The author,
** Split-representation = meaning + value?
being a social anthropologist, and not a linguist, can only try to explain briefly
to which specific features of kinship systems he is referring in this attempt
toward a generalized formulation. Since the general lines of his interpretation
have been fully developed elsewhere,[16] short sketches were deemed sufficient
for the purpose of this paper.


If the general characteristics of the kinship systems of given geographical
We may now ask whether, in extending the concept of communication so
areas, which we have tried to bring into juxtaposition with equally general
as to make it include exogamy and the rules flowing from the
cha,racteristics of the linguistic structures of those areas, are recognized by  
prohibition of in- cest, we may not, reciprocally, achieve insight
linguists as an approach to equivalences of their own observations, then it  
into a problem that is still very obscure, that of the origin of
will be apparent, in terms of our preceding discussion, that we are much closer
language. For marriage regulations, in relation to language, represent
to the understanding of the fundamental characteristics of social life than we
a complex much more rough and archaic than the latter. It is generally
have been accustomed to think.  
recognized that words are signs: but poets are practically the only
ones who know that words have also been values. As against this, women
are held by the social group to be values of the most essential kind,
though we have difficulty in understanding how these values become
integrated in systems endowed with a significant function. This
ambiguity is clearly manifested in the reactions of persons who, on
the basis of the analysis of social structures referred to,[9] have
laid against it the charge of "anti-feminism," because women are
referred to as objects.[10] Of course, it may be disturbing to some to
have women conceived as mere parts of a meaningful system. However,
one should keep in mind that the processes by which phonemes and words
have lost -- even though in an illusory manner -- their character of
value, to become reduced to pure signs, will never lead to the same
results in matters concerning women. For words do not speak, while
women do; as producers of signs, they can never be reduced to the
status of symbols or tokens. But it is for this very reason that the
position of women, as actually found in this system of communication
between men that is made up of marriage regulations and kinship
nomenclature, may afford us a workable image of the type of
relationships that could have existed at a very early period in the
development of language, between human beings and their words. As in
the case of women, the original impulse which compelled men to
exchange words must be sought for in that split-representa- tion which
pertains to the symbolic function. For, since certain terms are
simultaneously perceived as having a value both for the speaker and
the listener, the only way to resolve this contradiction is in the
exchange of complementary values, to which all social existence
reduces itself.


  The road will then be open for a comparative structural analysis of customs,  
== Hypothesis: are different aspects of social life generated by the system code? ==
institutions, and accepted patterns of behavior. We will be in a position
   
to understand basic similarities between forms of social life, such as language,
These speculations may be judged utopian. Yet, granting that the
art, law, religion, that, on the surface, seem to differ greatly. At the same time,  
assump- tions made here are legitimate, a very important consequence
we will have the hope of overcoming the opposition between the collective
follows that is susceptible of immediate verification. That is, the
nature of culture and its manifestations in the individual, since the so-called
question may be raised whether the different aspects of social life
"collective consciousness" would, in the final analysis, be no more than the
(including even art and religion) can not only be studied by the
expression, on the plane of individual thought and behavior, of certain time and
methods, and with the help of concepts similar to those employed in
space modalities of these universal laws which make up the unconscious
linguistics, but also whether they do not constitute phenomena whose
activity of the mind.
inmost nature is the same as that of language. That is, in the words
of Voegelin, we may ask whether there are not only "operational" but
also "substantial comparabilities" between language and culture.[11]


ENDNOTES
== To verify, go deep ... ==


[1] Wiener, N., 1948, p. 189-191.  
How can this hypothesis be verified? It will be necessary to develop
the analysis of the different features of social life, either for a
given society or for a complex of societies, so that a deep enough
level can be reached to make it possible to cross from one to the
other; or to express the specific structure of each in terms of a sort
of general language, valid for each system separately and for all of
them taken together. It would thus be possible to ascertain if one had
reached their inner nature, and to determine if this pertained to the
same kind of reality. In order to develop this point, an experiment
can be at- tempted. It will consist, on the part of the
anthropologist, in translating the basic features of the kinship
systems from different parts of the world in terms general enough to
be meaningful to the linguist, and thus be equally applicable by the
latter to the description of the languages from the same regions. Both
could thus ascertain whether or not different types of communication
systems in the same societies -- that is, kinship and language -- are
or are not caused by identical unconscious structures. Should this be
the case, we would be assured of having reached a truly fundamental
formulation.  


[2] Jakobson, R.,1948.
== The data ==


[3] Kroeber, A. L. and Richardson, J., 1940.
If then, a substantial identity were assumed to exist between language
structure and kinship systems, one should find, in the following
regions of the world, languages whose structures would be of a type
comparable to kinship systems in the following terms:


[4] Teissier, G., 1936.
=== Indo-Eurpopean ===
* Simple terms, many combiniations


[5] Levi-Strauss,C., 1949,passim.  
1. Indo-European: As concerns the kinship systems, we find that the
mar- riage regulations of our contemporary civilization are entirely
based on the principle that, a few negative prescriptions being
granted, the density and fluidity of the population will achieve by
itself the same results which other societies have sought in more
complicated sets of rules; i.e. social cohesion obtained by marriage
in degrees far removed or even impossible to trace. This statistical
solution has its origin in a typical feature of most ancient Indo-
European systems. These belong, in the author's terminology, to a
simple formula of generalized reciprocity (formule simple de 1'6change
g6n6ralis6).[12] However, instead of prevailing between lineages, this
formula operates be- tween more complex units of the brastsvo type,
which actually are clusters of lineages, each of which enjoys a
certain freedom within the rigid framework of general reciprocity in
effect at the level of the cluster. Therefore, it can be said that a
characteristic feature of Indo-European kinship structure lies in the
fact that a problem set in simple terms always admits of many
solutions. Should the linguistic structure be homologous with the
kinship structure it would thus be possible to express the basic
feature of Indo-European lan- guages as follows: The languages have
simple structures, utilizing numerous elements. The opposition between
the simplicity of the structure and the multi- plicity of elements is
expressed in the fact that several elements compete to occupy the same
positions in the structure.


[6] Ibid., pp. 278-380.
=== Sino-Thibetan ===
* Simple elements, complex structures


[7] Ibid., pp. 558-566.  
2. Sino-Thibetan kinship systems exhibit quite a different type of
complex- ity. They belong to or derive directly from the simplest form
of general reci- procity, namely mother's brother's daughter marriage,
so that, as has been shown,[13] while this type of marriage insures
social cohesion in the simplest way, at the same time it permits this
to be indefinitely extended so as to in- clude any number of
participants.  


[8] Ibid., pp. 547-550.  
Translated into more general terms applicable to language that would
correspond to the following linguistic pattern, we may say that the
structure is complex, while the elements are few, a feature that may
be related to the tonal structure of these languages.


[9] Ibid., p. 616.
=== African ===
* Intermediate between 1 and 2


[10] Ibid., p. 45 sq.  
3. The typical feature of African kinship systems is the extension of
the bride-wealth system, coupled with a rather frequent prohibition on
marriage with the wife's brother's wife. The joint result is a system
of general reciproc- ity already more complex than the one with the
mother's brother's daughter, while the types of unions resulting from
the circulation of the marriage-price approaches, to some extent, the
statistical mechanism operating in our own society.  


[11] "Language and Culture: substantial and operational comparabilities" was the title given
Therefore one could say that African languages have several modalities
by C. F. Voegelin to the symposium held at the 29th International Congress of Arnericanists,
corresponding in general to a position intermediate between 1) and 2).
New York, 5-12 September, 1949, where these reflections were first offered.  


[12] LBvi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 583-591.
=== Oceanic ===
* Simple structure, few elements


[13] Ibid., 1949, pp. 291-380.  
4. The widely recognized features of Oceanic kinship systems seem to
lead to the following formulation of the basic characteristics of the
linguistic pat- tern: simple structure and few elements.


[14] From this point of view, G. P. Murdock's suggestion that the Crow-Omaha type be merged
=== American ===
with the Miwok type (1949, pp. 224,340) should be challenged.
* Many elements, simple structures


[15] Levi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 228-233.
5. The originality of American kinship systems lies with the so-called
Crow- Omaha type which should be carefully distinguished from other
types showing -the same disregard for generation levels.[14] The
important point with the Crow- Omaha type is not that two kinds of
cross-cousins are classified in different generation levels, but
rather that they are classified with consanguineous kin instead of
with affinal kin as it occurs, for instance, in the Miwok system. But
systems of the Miwok type belong equally to the Old and the New World;
while when considering the differential systems just referred to as
Crow- Omaha, one must admit that, apart from a few exceptions, these
are only typi- cal for the New World. It can be shown that this quite
exceptional feature of the Crow-Omaha system results from the
simultaneous application of the two simple formulas of reciprocity,
both special and general (tchange restreint and echange
generalise),[15] which elsewhere in the world were generally
considered to be incompatible. It thus became possible to achieve
marriage within remote degrees by using simultaneously two simple
formulas, each of which independ- ently applied could only have led to
different kinds of cross-cousin marriages. The linguistic pattern
corresponding to that situation would be that cer- tain of the
American languages offer a relatively high number of elements, which
succeed in becoming organized into relatively simple structures by
com- pelling these to assume an asymmetrical form.


[16] Ibid.
= Concluding remarks =


BIBLIOGRAPHY
== Up to linguists to interpret the test ==


JAKOBSON, R., 1948, The phonemic and grammatical aspect of language in their interrelations.  
It must be kept in mind that in the above highly tentative experiment,
Actcs du 6O Congrds Internetional des linguistes, Paris.  
the anthropologist proceeds from what is known to what is unknown to
him: namely from kinship structures to linguistic structures. Whether
or not the differential characteristics thus outlined have a meaning
in so far as the re- spective languages are concerned, remains for the
linguist to decide. The author, being a social anthropologist, and not
a linguist, can only try to explain briefly to which specific features
of kinship systems he is referring in this attempt toward a
generalized formulation. Since the general lines of his interpretation
have been fully developed elsewhere,[16] short sketches were deemed
sufficient for the purpose of this paper.  


KBOEBER,A. L., and J. RICHARDSON, 1940, Three centuries of women's dress fashions. Anthro-
== If valid, then we are much closer to the goal ==
pologicd Records, Berkeley.


LEVI-STRAUSS, C., 1949, La Str~turcs &brnentuires de la Parentb, Paris.  
If the general characteristics of the kinship systems of given
geographical areas, which we have tried to bring into juxtaposition
with equally general characteristics of the linguistic structures of
those areas, are recognized by linguists as an approach to
equivalences of their own observations, then it will be apparent, in
terms of our preceding discussion, that we are much closer to the
understanding of the fundamental characteristics of social life than
we have been accustomed to think.  


MURDOCH, ,G. P., 1949, Social Structure, New York.
== Toward a comparative structural analysis of institutions ==


TEISSIER, G., 1936, La description mathkmatique des faits biologiques, Revue de M6taphysique
The road will then be open for a comparative structural analysis of
et de Morale, Paris, Jan.  
customs, institutions, and accepted patterns of behavior. We will be
in a position to understand basic similarities between forms of social
life, such as language, art, law, religion, that, on the surface, seem
to differ greatly. At the same time, we will have the hope of
overcoming the opposition between the collective nature of culture and
its manifestations in the individual, since the so-called "collective
consciousness" would, in the final analysis, be no more than the
expression, on the plane of individual thought and behavior, of
certain time and space modalities of these universal laws which make
up the unconscious activity of the mind.


  WIENER, N., 1948, Cybernetics, or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine,  
 
Paris, Cambridge, New York.
= ENDNOTES =
 
[1] Wiener, N., 1948, p. 189-191.
 
[2] Jakobson, R.,1948.
 
[3] Kroeber, A. L. and Richardson, J., 1940.
 
[4] Teissier, G., 1936.
 
[5] Levi-Strauss,C., 1949,passim.
 
[6] Ibid., pp. 278-380.
 
[7] Ibid., pp. 558-566.
 
[8] Ibid., pp. 547-550.
 
[9] Ibid., p. 616.
 
[10] Ibid., p. 45 sq.
 
[11] "Language and Culture: substantial and operational comparabilities" was the title given by C. F. Voegelin to the symposium held at the 29th International Congress of Arnericanists, New York, 5-12 September, 1949, where these reflections were first offered.
 
[12] LBvi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 583-591.
 
[13] Ibid., 1949, pp. 291-380.
 
[14] From this point of view, G. P. Murdock's suggestion that the Crow-Omaha type be merged with the Miwok type (1949, pp. 224,340) should be challenged.
 
[15] Levi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 228-233.
 
[16] Ibid.
 
= BIBLIOGRAPHY =
 
JAKOBSON, R., 1948, The phonemic and grammatical aspect of language
in their interrelations.
Actcs du 6O Congrds Internetional des linguistes, Paris.
<br/>
KBOEBER, A. L., and J. RICHARDSON, 1940, Three centuries of women's
dress fashions. Anthro-
pologicd Records, Berkeley.
<br/>
LEVI-STRAUSS, C., 1949, La Structures Elementaires de la Parente,
Paris.
<br/>
MURDOCH, G. P., 1949, Social Structure, New York.
<br/>
TEISSIER, G., 1936, La description mathkmatique des faits
biologiques, Revue de M6taphysique
et de Morale, Paris, Jan.
<br/>
WIENER, N., 1948, Cybernetics, or Control and Communication in the
Animal and the Machine,  
Paris, Cambridge, New York.

Latest revision as of 17:42, 6 October 2007

Go to Main Page

Language and the Analysis of Social Laws

Claude Lévi-Strauss

American Anthropologist, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2. (Apr. -Jun., 1951), pp. 155-163.

Stable URL: JSTOR Link

Can there be a cybernetic anthropology?

Wiener doesn't think so

IN A recent work, whose importance from the point of view of the future of the social sciences can hardly be overestimated, Wiener poses, and re- solves in the negative, the question of a possible extension to the social sciences of the mathematical methods of prediction which have made possible the construction of the great modern electronic machines. He justifies his position by two arguments.[1]

The problem of reflexivity (as I call it)

In the first place, he maintains that the nature of the social sciences is such that it is inevitable that their very development must have repercussions on the object of their investigation. The coupling of the observer with the observed phenomenon is well known to contemporary scientific thought, and, in a sense, it illustrates a universal situation. But it is negligible in fields which are ripe for the most advanced mathematical investigation; as, for example, in astrophysics, where the object has such vast dimensions that the influence of the observer need not be taken into account, or in atomic physics, where the object is so small that we are only interested in average mass effects in which the effect of bias on the part of the observer plays no role. In the field of the social sciences, on the contrary, the object of study is necessarily affected by the intervention of the observer, and the resulting modifications are on the same scale as the phenomena that are studied.

The problem of the short run

In the second place, Wiener observes that the phenomena subjected to sociological or anthropological inquiry are defined within our own sphere of interests; they concern questions of the life, education, career, and death of individuals. Therefore the statistical runs available for the study of a given phenomenon are always far too short to lay the foundation of a valid induction. Mathematical analysis in the field of social sciences, he concludes, can bring results which should be of as little interest to the social scientist as those of the statistical study of a gas would be to an individual about the size of a molecule.

But Wiener focuses on one kind of data

These objections seem difficult to refute when they are examined in terms of the investigations toward which their author has directed them, the data of research monographs and of applied anthropology. In such cases, we are deal- ing with a study of individual behavior, directed by an observer who is him- self an individual; or with a study of a culture, a national character, or a pat- tern, by an observer who cannot dissociate himself completely from his culture, or from the culture out of which his working hypotheses and his methods of observation, which are themselves cultural patterns, are derived.

We should use language as our model

There is, however, at least one area of the social sciences where Wiener's objections do not seem to be applicable, where the conditions which he sets as a requirement for a valid mathematical study seem to find themselves rigorously met. This is the field of language, when studied in the light of struc- tural linguistics, with particular reference to phonemics.

Language not affected by reflexivity

  • Language's rules are unconscious and unaffected by awareness of them

Language is a social phenomenon; and, of all social phenomena, it is the one which manifests to the greatest degree two fundamental characteristics which make it susceptible of scientific study. In the first place, much of lin- guistic behavior lies on the level of unconscious thought. When we speak, we are not conscious of the syntactic and morphological laws of our language. Moreover, we are not ordinarily conscious of the phonemes that we employ to convey different meanings; and we are rarely, if ever, conscious of the phono- logical oppositions which reduce each phoneme to a bundle of differential features. This absence of consciousness, moreover, still holds when we do be- come aware of the grammar or the phonemics of our language. For, while this awareness is but the privilege of the scholar, language, as a matter of fact, lives and develops only as a collective construct; and even the scholar's lin- guistic knowledge always remains dissociated from his experience as a speaking agent, for his mode of speech is not affected by his ability to interpret his lan- guage on a higher level. We may say, then, that as concerns language, we need not fear the influence of the observer on the observed phenomenon, because the observer cannot modify the phenomenon merely by becoming conscious of it.

Language is ancient

Furthermore, as regards Wiener's second point, we know that language appeared very early in human history. Therefore, even if we can study it scientifically only when written documents are available, writing itself goes back a considerable distance, and furnishes long enough runs to make language a valid subject for mathematical analysis. For example, the series we have at our disposal in studying Indo-European, Semitic or Sino-Thibetan languages is about four or five thousand years old. And, where a comparable temporal dimension is lacking, the multiplicity of coexistent forms furnishes, for several other linguistic families, a spatial dimension that is no less valuable.

We thus find in language a social phenomenon which manifests both in- dependence of the object and long statistical runs; which would seem to indi- cate that language is a phenomenon fully qualified to satisfy the demands of mathematicians for the type of analysis Wiener suggests.

Language lends itself to computation

  • Note L-S's conflation of cybernetics with computation
  • L-S shows his interest in database technology here (as elsewhere)
  • Basic idea: structure = elements + rules of combination

It is, in fact, difficult to see why certain linguistic problems could not be solved by modern calculating machines. With knowledge of the phonological structure of a language and the laws which govern the grouping of consonants and vowels, a student could easily use a machine to compute all the combina- tions of phonemes constituting the words of n syllables existing in the vocabu- lary, or even the number of combinations compatible with the structure of the language under consideration, such as previously defined. With a machine into which would be "fed" the equations regulating the types of structures with which phonemics usually deals, the repertory of sound which human speech organs can emit, and the minimal differential values, determined by psycho-physiological methods, which distinguish between the phonemes closest to one another, one would doubtless be able to obtain a computation of the totality of phonological structures for n oppositions (n being as high as one wished). One could thus construct a sort of periodic table of linguistic struc- tures that would be comparable to the table of elements which Mendeleieff introduced into modern chemistry. It would then only remain for us to check the place of known languages in this table, to identify the positions and the relationships of the languages whose first-hand study is still too imperfect to give us a proper theoretical knowledge of them, and to discover the place of languages that have disappeared, are unknown, yet to come,, or simply possible.

An example from Jakobson

  • Metastructure
  • "Law of the Group" (See

L-S 1955)

To add a last example: Jakobson has recently suggested that a language may possess several coexisting phonological structures, each of which may intervene in a different kind of grammatical operation.[2] Since there must ob- viously be a relationship between the different structural modalities of the same language, we arrive at the concept of a "metastructure" which would be some- thing like the law of the group (loi du groupe) consisting of its modal structures. If all of these modalities could be analyzed by our machine, established mathe- matical methods would permit it to construct the "metastructure" of the language, which would in certain complex cases be so intricate as to make it difficult, if not impossible, to achieve on the basis of purely empirical investi- gation.

The Model of Language

  • Language = phonemes + rules of combination
  • "Universal laws which regulate the unconscious activities of the

mind"

  • Criteria for structure:
    1. is unconscious
    2. has elements
    3. has rules
    4. does communication
  • Grammar is a good synonym

The problem under discussion here can, then, be defined as follows. Among all social phenomena, language alone has thus far been studied in a manner which permits it to serve as the object of truly scientific analysis, allowing us to understand its formative process and to predict its mode of change. This results from modern researches into the problems of phonemics, which have reached beyond the superficial conscious and historical expression of linguistic phenomena to attain fundamental and objective realities consisting of systems of relations which are the products of unconscious thought processes. The question which now arises is this: is it possible to effect a similar reduction in the analysis of other forms of social phenomena? If so, would this analysis lead to the same result? And if the answer to this last question is in the affirma- tive, can we conclude that all forms of social life are substantially of the same nature-that is, do they consist of systems of behavior that represent the pro- jection, on the level of conscious and socialized thought, of universal laws which regulate the unconscious activities of the mind? Obviously, no attempt can be made here to do more than to sketch this problem by indicating certain points of reference and projecting the principal lines along which its orientation might be effective.

The example of Kroeber on fashion

  • About Kroeber's essay:
    • Women’s dress fashion over 300 years
    • Skirt length changed in a periodic cycle.
    • No direct cause (political or economic cycles) -- cannot be explained by outside factors; evolves according to its own internal laws.
    • This independent cultural realm = the "superorganic"

Some of the researches of Kroeber appear to be of the greatest importance in suggesting approaches to our problem, particularly his work on changes in the styles of women's dress[3] Fashion actually is, in the highest degree, a phe- nomenon which depends on the unconscious activity of the mind. We rarely take note of why a particular style pleases us, or falls into disuse. Kroeber has demonstrated that this seemingly arbitrary evolution follows definite laws. These laws cannot be reached by purely empirical observation, or by intuitive consideration of phenomena, but result from measuring some basic relation- ships between the various elements of costume. The relationship thus obtained can be expressed in terms of mathematical functions, whose values, calculated at a given moment, make prediction possible.

Teissier on zoology

Kroeber has thus shown how even such a highly arbitrary aspect of social behavior is susceptible of scientific study. His method may be usefully com- pared not only with that of structural linguistics, but also with that of the natural sciences. There is a remarkable analogy between these researches and those of a contemporary biologist, G. Teissier, on the growth of the organs of certain crustaceans.[4] Teissier has shown that, in order to formulate the laws of this growth, it has been necessary to consider the relative dimensions of the component parts of the claws, and not the exterior forms of these organs. There, relationships allow us to derive constants-termed parameters-out of which it is possible to derive the laws which govern the development of these organisms. The object of a scientific zoology, in these terms, is thus not ulti- mately concerned with the forms of animals and their organs as they are usual- ly perceived, but is to establish certain abstract and measurable relationships, which constitute the basic nature of the phenomena under study.

Levi-Strauss on kinship

  • Describes results from The Elementary Structures of Kinship.
  • Elements = partners, groups, households
  • Rules = incest prohibition, marriage rules, inheritance, locality

An analogous method has been followed in studying certain features of social organization, particularly marriage rules and kinship systems.[5] It has been shown that the complete set of marriage regulations operating in human societies, and usually classified under different headings such as incest prohibi- tions, preferential forms of marriage, and the like, can be interpreted as being so many different ways of insuring the circulation of women within the social group, or, of substituting the mechanism of a sociologically determined affinity for that of a biologically determined consanguinity. Proceeding from this hypothesis, it would only be neccesary to make a mathematical study of every possible type of exchange between npartners to enable one almost automatical- ly to arrive at every type of marriage rule actually operating in living societies and, eventually, to discover others which are merely possible; one would also understand their function and the relationships between each type and the others.

Reciprocity as special case of exchange

This approach was fully validated by the demonstration, reached by pure deduction, that the mechanisms of reciprocity known to classical anthropology -- namely, those based on dual organization and exchange-marriage between two partners or whose number is a multiple of two-are but a special instance of a wider kind of reciprocity between any number of partners. This fact has tended to remain unnoticed, because the partners in those matings, instead of giving and receiving from one another, do not give to those from whom they receive, and do not receive from those to whom they give.,They give to and receive from different partners to whom they are bound by a relationship that operates only in one direction.

This type of organization, no less important than the moiety system, has thus far been observed and described only imperfectly and incidentally. Start- ing with the results of mathematical study, data had to be compiled; thus, the real extension of the system was shown and its first theoretical analysis ffered.[6] At the same time, it became possible to explain the more general features of marriage rules such as preferential marriage between bilateral cross-cousins or with only one kind of cross-cousin, on the father's side (patrilateral), or on that of the mother (matrilateral). Thus, for example, though such customs had been unintelligible to anthropologists,[7] they were perfectly clear when regarded as illustrating different modalities of the laws of exchange. In turn, these were reduced to a still more basic relationship between the rules of residence and the rules of descent.[8]

The result of viewing kinship and marriage as communication

  • Clothing and women are signals

Now, these results have only been achieved by treating marriage regula- tions and kinship systems as a kind of language, a set of processes permitting the establishment, between individuals and groups, of a certain type of com- munication. That the mediating factor, in this case, should be the women of the group, who are circulated between clans, lineages, or families, in place of the words of the group, which are circulated between individuals, does not at all change the fact that the essential ~pect of the phenomenon is identical in both cases.

The Origin of Language

Kinship may help shed light on the origin of language

  • Kinship is more static and has more data
  • If it is a communication system, and if all communication systems share a common code, then kinship theory can shed light on language
  • "The original impulse which compelled men to exchange words must be sought for in that split-representation which pertains to the symbolic function."
    • Split-representation = meaning + value?

We may now ask whether, in extending the concept of communication so as to make it include exogamy and the rules flowing from the prohibition of in- cest, we may not, reciprocally, achieve insight into a problem that is still very obscure, that of the origin of language. For marriage regulations, in relation to language, represent a complex much more rough and archaic than the latter. It is generally recognized that words are signs: but poets are practically the only ones who know that words have also been values. As against this, women are held by the social group to be values of the most essential kind, though we have difficulty in understanding how these values become integrated in systems endowed with a significant function. This ambiguity is clearly manifested in the reactions of persons who, on the basis of the analysis of social structures referred to,[9] have laid against it the charge of "anti-feminism," because women are referred to as objects.[10] Of course, it may be disturbing to some to have women conceived as mere parts of a meaningful system. However, one should keep in mind that the processes by which phonemes and words have lost -- even though in an illusory manner -- their character of value, to become reduced to pure signs, will never lead to the same results in matters concerning women. For words do not speak, while women do; as producers of signs, they can never be reduced to the status of symbols or tokens. But it is for this very reason that the position of women, as actually found in this system of communication between men that is made up of marriage regulations and kinship nomenclature, may afford us a workable image of the type of relationships that could have existed at a very early period in the development of language, between human beings and their words. As in the case of women, the original impulse which compelled men to exchange words must be sought for in that split-representa- tion which pertains to the symbolic function. For, since certain terms are simultaneously perceived as having a value both for the speaker and the listener, the only way to resolve this contradiction is in the exchange of complementary values, to which all social existence reduces itself.

Hypothesis: are different aspects of social life generated by the system code?

These speculations may be judged utopian. Yet, granting that the assump- tions made here are legitimate, a very important consequence follows that is susceptible of immediate verification. That is, the question may be raised whether the different aspects of social life (including even art and religion) can not only be studied by the methods, and with the help of concepts similar to those employed in linguistics, but also whether they do not constitute phenomena whose inmost nature is the same as that of language. That is, in the words of Voegelin, we may ask whether there are not only "operational" but also "substantial comparabilities" between language and culture.[11]

To verify, go deep ...

How can this hypothesis be verified? It will be necessary to develop the analysis of the different features of social life, either for a given society or for a complex of societies, so that a deep enough level can be reached to make it possible to cross from one to the other; or to express the specific structure of each in terms of a sort of general language, valid for each system separately and for all of them taken together. It would thus be possible to ascertain if one had reached their inner nature, and to determine if this pertained to the same kind of reality. In order to develop this point, an experiment can be at- tempted. It will consist, on the part of the anthropologist, in translating the basic features of the kinship systems from different parts of the world in terms general enough to be meaningful to the linguist, and thus be equally applicable by the latter to the description of the languages from the same regions. Both could thus ascertain whether or not different types of communication systems in the same societies -- that is, kinship and language -- are or are not caused by identical unconscious structures. Should this be the case, we would be assured of having reached a truly fundamental formulation.

The data

If then, a substantial identity were assumed to exist between language structure and kinship systems, one should find, in the following regions of the world, languages whose structures would be of a type comparable to kinship systems in the following terms:

Indo-Eurpopean

  • Simple terms, many combiniations

1. Indo-European: As concerns the kinship systems, we find that the mar- riage regulations of our contemporary civilization are entirely based on the principle that, a few negative prescriptions being granted, the density and fluidity of the population will achieve by itself the same results which other societies have sought in more complicated sets of rules; i.e. social cohesion obtained by marriage in degrees far removed or even impossible to trace. This statistical solution has its origin in a typical feature of most ancient Indo- European systems. These belong, in the author's terminology, to a simple formula of generalized reciprocity (formule simple de 1'6change g6n6ralis6).[12] However, instead of prevailing between lineages, this formula operates be- tween more complex units of the brastsvo type, which actually are clusters of lineages, each of which enjoys a certain freedom within the rigid framework of general reciprocity in effect at the level of the cluster. Therefore, it can be said that a characteristic feature of Indo-European kinship structure lies in the fact that a problem set in simple terms always admits of many solutions. Should the linguistic structure be homologous with the kinship structure it would thus be possible to express the basic feature of Indo-European lan- guages as follows: The languages have simple structures, utilizing numerous elements. The opposition between the simplicity of the structure and the multi- plicity of elements is expressed in the fact that several elements compete to occupy the same positions in the structure.

Sino-Thibetan

  • Simple elements, complex structures

2. Sino-Thibetan kinship systems exhibit quite a different type of complex- ity. They belong to or derive directly from the simplest form of general reci- procity, namely mother's brother's daughter marriage, so that, as has been shown,[13] while this type of marriage insures social cohesion in the simplest way, at the same time it permits this to be indefinitely extended so as to in- clude any number of participants.

Translated into more general terms applicable to language that would correspond to the following linguistic pattern, we may say that the structure is complex, while the elements are few, a feature that may be related to the tonal structure of these languages.

African

  • Intermediate between 1 and 2

3. The typical feature of African kinship systems is the extension of the bride-wealth system, coupled with a rather frequent prohibition on marriage with the wife's brother's wife. The joint result is a system of general reciproc- ity already more complex than the one with the mother's brother's daughter, while the types of unions resulting from the circulation of the marriage-price approaches, to some extent, the statistical mechanism operating in our own society.

Therefore one could say that African languages have several modalities corresponding in general to a position intermediate between 1) and 2).

Oceanic

  • Simple structure, few elements

4. The widely recognized features of Oceanic kinship systems seem to lead to the following formulation of the basic characteristics of the linguistic pat- tern: simple structure and few elements.

American

  • Many elements, simple structures

5. The originality of American kinship systems lies with the so-called Crow- Omaha type which should be carefully distinguished from other types showing -the same disregard for generation levels.[14] The important point with the Crow- Omaha type is not that two kinds of cross-cousins are classified in different generation levels, but rather that they are classified with consanguineous kin instead of with affinal kin as it occurs, for instance, in the Miwok system. But systems of the Miwok type belong equally to the Old and the New World; while when considering the differential systems just referred to as Crow- Omaha, one must admit that, apart from a few exceptions, these are only typi- cal for the New World. It can be shown that this quite exceptional feature of the Crow-Omaha system results from the simultaneous application of the two simple formulas of reciprocity, both special and general (tchange restreint and echange generalise),[15] which elsewhere in the world were generally considered to be incompatible. It thus became possible to achieve marriage within remote degrees by using simultaneously two simple formulas, each of which independ- ently applied could only have led to different kinds of cross-cousin marriages. The linguistic pattern corresponding to that situation would be that cer- tain of the American languages offer a relatively high number of elements, which succeed in becoming organized into relatively simple structures by com- pelling these to assume an asymmetrical form.

Concluding remarks

Up to linguists to interpret the test

It must be kept in mind that in the above highly tentative experiment, the anthropologist proceeds from what is known to what is unknown to him: namely from kinship structures to linguistic structures. Whether or not the differential characteristics thus outlined have a meaning in so far as the re- spective languages are concerned, remains for the linguist to decide. The author, being a social anthropologist, and not a linguist, can only try to explain briefly to which specific features of kinship systems he is referring in this attempt toward a generalized formulation. Since the general lines of his interpretation have been fully developed elsewhere,[16] short sketches were deemed sufficient for the purpose of this paper.

If valid, then we are much closer to the goal

If the general characteristics of the kinship systems of given geographical areas, which we have tried to bring into juxtaposition with equally general characteristics of the linguistic structures of those areas, are recognized by linguists as an approach to equivalences of their own observations, then it will be apparent, in terms of our preceding discussion, that we are much closer to the understanding of the fundamental characteristics of social life than we have been accustomed to think.

Toward a comparative structural analysis of institutions

The road will then be open for a comparative structural analysis of customs, institutions, and accepted patterns of behavior. We will be in a position to understand basic similarities between forms of social life, such as language, art, law, religion, that, on the surface, seem to differ greatly. At the same time, we will have the hope of overcoming the opposition between the collective nature of culture and its manifestations in the individual, since the so-called "collective consciousness" would, in the final analysis, be no more than the expression, on the plane of individual thought and behavior, of certain time and space modalities of these universal laws which make up the unconscious activity of the mind.


ENDNOTES

[1] Wiener, N., 1948, p. 189-191.

[2] Jakobson, R.,1948.

[3] Kroeber, A. L. and Richardson, J., 1940.

[4] Teissier, G., 1936.

[5] Levi-Strauss,C., 1949,passim.

[6] Ibid., pp. 278-380.

[7] Ibid., pp. 558-566.

[8] Ibid., pp. 547-550.

[9] Ibid., p. 616.

[10] Ibid., p. 45 sq.

[11] "Language and Culture: substantial and operational comparabilities" was the title given by C. F. Voegelin to the symposium held at the 29th International Congress of Arnericanists, New York, 5-12 September, 1949, where these reflections were first offered.

[12] LBvi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 583-591.

[13] Ibid., 1949, pp. 291-380.

[14] From this point of view, G. P. Murdock's suggestion that the Crow-Omaha type be merged with the Miwok type (1949, pp. 224,340) should be challenged.

[15] Levi-Strauss, C., 1949, pp. 228-233.

[16] Ibid.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

JAKOBSON, R., 1948, The phonemic and grammatical aspect of language in their interrelations. Actcs du 6O Congrds Internetional des linguistes, Paris.
KBOEBER, A. L., and J. RICHARDSON, 1940, Three centuries of women's dress fashions. Anthro- pologicd Records, Berkeley.
LEVI-STRAUSS, C., 1949, La Structures Elementaires de la Parente, Paris.
MURDOCH, G. P., 1949, Social Structure, New York.
TEISSIER, G., 1936, La description mathkmatique des faits biologiques, Revue de M6taphysique et de Morale, Paris, Jan.
WIENER, N., 1948, Cybernetics, or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine, Paris, Cambridge, New York.