William Baumol's Fairness Assumption: Difference between revisions

From Dickinson College Wiki
Jump to navigationJump to search
Hartl (talk | contribs)
No edit summary
Line 16: Line 16:
*'''Superfairness'''<nowiki>:</nowiki>
*'''Superfairness'''<nowiki>:</nowiki>
::If the bundles held by both A and B can be reduced without giving rise to envy, then the distribution is ''superfair''.
::If the bundles held by both A and B can be reduced without giving rise to envy, then the distribution is ''superfair''.
*'''Fairness Boundary'''<nowiki>:</nowiki>
::The borderline between distributions which A considers to be unfair, and those that A considers to be more than fair.


=<center>Who ''cares'' about fairness?</center>=
=<center>Who ''cares'' about fairness?</center>=
Line 25: Line 28:


<center>[[building and using an Edgeworth Box to map fair distributions]]</center>
<center>[[building and using an Edgeworth Box to map fair distributions]]</center>
=<center>Characteristics of Superfairness</center>=
The concept of envy requires that each party evaluate the bundles received by others based on their own preferences.  The bundles that occur at the intersection of an individual, A's, indifference curves and their mirror image (A's indifference curves that depict the valuation of bundles received by another individual, B) are said to be fair, as A is clearly indifferent between either bundle at that point.  By tracing out an infinite number of these mirrored indifference curves, we can map A's fairness boundary based on these intersections.  In exactly the same way we can construct the fairness boundary for B based on B's indifference curves and their mirror images.
By looking at the fairness boundaries using an edgeworth box it becomes very easy to see how superfair outcomes can arise.  By comparing bundles that lie on A's fairness boundary with those that lie above it, it is easy to determine that while the bundle that lies on the fairness boundary is marginally fair to A, the bundle that lies above the fairness boundary is more than fair. Likewise, B would consider any point below his fairness boundary to be more than fair.  Therefore, any point in the region that lies above A's fairness boundary and below B's represents a superfair distribution.


=<center>Multistage Superfairness</center>=
=<center>Multistage Superfairness</center>=


=<center>Applications</center>=
=<center>Applications</center>=

Revision as of 01:19, 5 May 2006

Overview | What Is Fairness? | Fairness In Game Theory | Retaliation and Reciprocity | William Baumol's Fairness Assumption | The Ultimatum Game Under Baumol's Fairness Assumption | Fairness Theory Homepage





Definitions

For convenience, the below definitions assume a world with two individuals, A and B, and two goods, X and Y


  • Envy:
If A prefers to his own bundle, the bundle of goods held by B, A is said to envy B.
  • Fairness:
The distribution of goods X and Y is fair if no envy is involved.
  • Superfairness:
If the bundles held by both A and B can be reduced without giving rise to envy, then the distribution is superfair.
  • Fairness Boundary:
The borderline between distributions which A considers to be unfair, and those that A considers to be more than fair.

Who cares about fairness?

  • If preferences are strictly selfish, then why does fairness matter?
Selfish people are selfishly worried about others treating them unfairly. As a result, it is often times these innately selfish individuals who insist on rules of fairness. Fairness rules are accepted by selfish individuals as an insurance arrangement to make sure that they will not be mistreated. They pay for this insurance by guaranteeing others that they too will not be mistreated.

The Edgeworth Box

building and using an Edgeworth Box to map fair distributions

Characteristics of Superfairness

The concept of envy requires that each party evaluate the bundles received by others based on their own preferences. The bundles that occur at the intersection of an individual, A's, indifference curves and their mirror image (A's indifference curves that depict the valuation of bundles received by another individual, B) are said to be fair, as A is clearly indifferent between either bundle at that point. By tracing out an infinite number of these mirrored indifference curves, we can map A's fairness boundary based on these intersections. In exactly the same way we can construct the fairness boundary for B based on B's indifference curves and their mirror images.

By looking at the fairness boundaries using an edgeworth box it becomes very easy to see how superfair outcomes can arise. By comparing bundles that lie on A's fairness boundary with those that lie above it, it is easy to determine that while the bundle that lies on the fairness boundary is marginally fair to A, the bundle that lies above the fairness boundary is more than fair. Likewise, B would consider any point below his fairness boundary to be more than fair. Therefore, any point in the region that lies above A's fairness boundary and below B's represents a superfair distribution.

Multistage Superfairness

Applications